K Seles
3 min readOct 24, 2021

--

Following are excerpts from 'God-intoxicated man

The philosopher who questioned the existence of the world'

CLARE CARLISLE AND

YITZHAK Y. MELAMED

MAY 15, 2020

“Despite many readings of the Ethics which make

the phrase Deus sive Natura a cornerstone of Spinoza’s metaphysical system, to say that everything,

including the world as a whole, is in God – a position

now labelled “panentheism” – is quite different from

claiming that the world is God, the view usually

known as “pantheism”. Spinoza’s panentheism

leaves room for the idea that God exceeds, or transcends, the sum total of all things (or “modes”). The

God of the Ethics certainly transcends what we normally call “nature”. This is inseparable from the fact

that Spinoza’s God transcends human knowledge

and experience. God’s essence is expressed through

an infinity of attributes (or distinct ways of being),

and we have access to just two of these attributes:

thought and extension.”

“By the end of the eighteenth century, however, a

new assessment of Spinoza’s religiosity had

emerged. The Lithuanian philosopher Salomon Maimon – admired by Kant as “the sharpest and deepest

of his critics” – came to Spinoza after studying the

Talmud, the Kabbalah and Maimonides. In 1792 Maimon’s Lebensgeschichte, or Autobiography, shocked

readers with the claim that “it is hard to fathom how

Spinoza’s system could have been made out to be

atheistic, since the two systems are diametrically

opposed. The atheist system denies the existence of

God; Spinoza’s denies the existence of the world.

Thus, Spinoza’s system should really be called acosmism”.

“Maimon helped inspire a new German Spinozism,

which found memorable expression in Novalis’s

description of Spinoza as a “God-intoxicated man”.

Suddenly the damned atheist became the hero of a

radical Romantic religiosity, which could claim to be

more religious than traditional orthodoxy (insofar as

it discovered God’s presence in all things), yet free

from the old illusions of an anthropomorphic God

and an anthropocentric faith, and from the abuses

of clericalism. Heinrich Heine summarized this view

in his Geschichte der Religion und Philosophie in

Deutschland (1835): “Only malice or lack of judgement could describe Spinoza’s teaching as ‘atheistic.’

No one has ever expressed himself more sublimely

about the divinity than Spinoza”.

“In the Ethics the difference between God and the

world lies in that humdrum yet cryptic word “in”:

“Whatever is, is in God [in Deo est]”. In 1943, Étienne Souriau, a brilliant yet now overlooked philosopher who contributed to a remarkable revival of

Spinoza in France, suggested that “the meaning of

the little word ‘in’ is the key to all Spinozism”. Is

the world dissolved (acosmism) or deified (pantheism) in God-or-Nature? Or is the world grounded in

a transcendent God in which real entities “live and

move and have their being”? And what difference

does this make to the way we understand ourselves,

and to how we live – which is the ultimate question

of the Ethics?”

“The recent explosion of Spinoza studies –

and of contemporary metaphysics and epistemology inspired by Spinoza – has resulted in a deep

reorientation in analytic as well as continental philosophy. In many ways, Spinoza is now replacing

Kant and Descartes as both the compass and the

watershed of modern thought.

Part of Spinoza’s allure is his willingness to follow

reason wherever it led him. Deliberately remaining

outside both Jewish and Christian communities, Spinoza gained a remarkably perspicacious insight into

taken-for-granted intuitions and prejudices. Recognizing no authority beyond the power of his arguments, he presented his reasoning in the most transparent manner, as if daring his opponents to

challenge the validity of his inferences.

While philosophical boldness and precision

underwrite the intellectual power of Spinozism, the

religious element of his thought remains crucial. For

centuries the Ethics has been religiously questionable, and when we read it today we should take the

question of religion seriously. This is best treated as

a genuinely open question, since Spinoza’s religion

does not fit easily into any pre-existent category.

Like Thomas Aquinas, he treated religio not as a

system of beliefs but as a virtue – the virtue of honouring God. In the Ethics he considers religio alongside other virtues such as piety, nobility, generosity

and fortitude. Without concealing his contempt for

superstitious, anthropomorphic images of God, Spinoza asks what it means to know – and love – the

God which grounds our being.”

--

--

K Seles
K Seles

Written by K Seles

Architect by vocation. Individualist by inclination. Political sociologist, anthropologist, rationalist, philosophist, and cosmologist by avocation.

No responses yet